Adversarial Sequence PredictionSSEC.doc

上传人:laozhun 文档编号:3021903 上传时间:2023-03-08 格式:DOC 页数:5 大小:61KB
返回 下载 相关 举报
Adversarial Sequence PredictionSSEC.doc_第1页
第1页 / 共5页
Adversarial Sequence PredictionSSEC.doc_第2页
第2页 / 共5页
Adversarial Sequence PredictionSSEC.doc_第3页
第3页 / 共5页
Adversarial Sequence PredictionSSEC.doc_第4页
第4页 / 共5页
Adversarial Sequence PredictionSSEC.doc_第5页
第5页 / 共5页
亲,该文档总共5页,全部预览完了,如果喜欢就下载吧!
资源描述

《Adversarial Sequence PredictionSSEC.doc》由会员分享,可在线阅读,更多相关《Adversarial Sequence PredictionSSEC.doc(5页珍藏版)》请在三一办公上搜索。

1、Adversarial Sequence PredictionBill HIBBARDUniversity of Wisconsin - MadisonAbstract. Sequence prediction is a key component of intelligence. This can be extended to define a game between intelligent agents. An analog of a result of Legg shows that this game is a computational resources arms race fo

2、r agents with enormous resources. Software experiments provide evidence that this is also true for agents with more modest resources. This arms race is a relevant issue for AI ethics. This paper also discusses physical limits on AGI theory.Keywords. Sequence prediction, AI ethics, physical limits on

3、 computing.IntroductionSchmidhuber, Hutter and Legg have created a novel theoretical approach to artificial general intelligence (AGI). They have defined idealized intelligent agents 1, 2 and used reinforcement learning as a framework for defining and measuring intelligence 3. In their framework an

4、agent interacts with its environment at a sequence of discrete times and its intelligence is measured by the sum of rewards it receives over the sequence of times, averaged over all environments. In order to maximize this sum, an intelligent agent must learn to predict future rewards based on past o

5、bservations and rewards. Hence, learning to predict sequences is an important part of intelligence.A realistic environment for an agent includes competition, in the form of other agents whose rewards depend on reducing the rewards of the first agent. To model this situation, this paper extends the f

6、ormalism of sequence prediction to a competition between two agents. Intuitively, the point of this paper is that agents with greater computational resources will win the competition. This point is established by a proof for agents with large resources and suggested by software experiments for agent

7、s with modest resources. This point has implications for AI ethics.1. Sequence PredictionIn a recent paper Legg investigates algorithms for predicting infinite computable binary sequences 4, which are a key component of his definition of intelligence. He proves that there can be no elegant predictio

8、n algorithm that learns to predict all computable binary sequences. However, as his Lemma 6.2 makes clear, the difficulty lies entirely with sequences that are very expensive to compute. In order to discuss this further, we need a few brief definitions. N is the set of positive integers, B = 0, 1 is

9、 a binary alphabet, B* is the set of finite binary sequences (including the empty sequence), and B is the set of infinite binary sequences. A generator g is a program for a universal Turing machine that writes a sequence w B to its output tape, and we write w = U(g). A predictor p is a program for a

10、 universal Turing machine that implements a total function B* B. We say that a predictor p learns to predict a sequence x1 x2 x3 B if there exists r N such that n r, p(x1 x2 x3 xn) = xn+1. Let C B denote the set of computable binary sequences computed by generators. Given a generator g such that w =

11、 U(g), let tg(n) denote the number of computation steps performed by g before the nth symbol of w is written.Now, given any computable monotonically increasing function f: N N, define Cf = w C | $g. U(g) = w and $r N, n r. tg(n) 400, f(n) is greater than Lloyds estimate for the number of computation

12、s performed in the history of the universe. The laws of physics are not settled so Lloyd may be wrong, but there is no evidence of infinite information processes in the universe. So in the physical world it is reasonable to accept Lemma 6.2 as defining an elegant universal sequence predictor. This p

13、redictor can learn to predict any sequence that can be generated in our universe. But, as defined in the proof of Lemma 6.2, this elegant predictor requires too much computing time to be implemented in our universe. So this still leaves open the question of whether there exist sequence predictors ef

14、ficient enough to be implemented in this universe and that can learn to predict any sequence that can be generated in this universe. It would be useful to have a mathematical definition of intelligence that includes a physically realistic limit on computational resources, as advocated by Wang 6.2. A

15、dversarial Sequence PredictionOne of the challenges for an intelligent mind in our world is competition from other intelligent minds. The sequences that we must learn to predict are often generated by minds that can observe our predictions and have an interest in preventing our accurate prediction.

16、In order to investigate this situation define an evader e and a predictor p as programs for a universal Turing machine that implement total functions B* B. A pair e and p play a game 7, where e produces a sequence x1 x2 x3 B according to xn+1 = e(y1 y2 y3 yn) and p produces a sequence y1 y2 y3 B acc

17、ording to yn+1 = p(x1 x2 x3 xn). The predictor p wins round n+1 if yn+1 = xn+1 and the evader e wins if yn+1 xn+1. We say that the predictor p learns to predict the evader e if there exists r N such that n r, yn = xn and we say the evader e learns to evade the predictor p if there exists r N such th

18、at n r, yn xn.Note that an evader whose sequence of output symbols is independent of the prediction sequence is just a generator (the evader implements a function B* B but is actually a program for a universal Turing machine that can write to its output tape while ignoring symbols from its input tap

19、e). Hence any universal predictor for evaders will also serve as a universal predictor for generators.Also note the symmetry between evaders and predictors. Given a predictor p and an evader e, define an evader e by the program that implements p modified to complement the binary symbols it writes to

20、 its output tape and define a predictor p by the program that implements e modified to complement the binary symbols it reads from its input tape. Then p learns to predict e if and only if e learns to evade p.Given any computable monotonically increasing function f: N N, define Ef = the set of evade

21、rs e such that $r N, n r. te(n) r. tp(n) r. te(n) m the sequence generated by e will be in Wn. For each evader e previous to e in the lexicographical order ask if there exists r max(m, length of program implementing e) such that te(r+1) m means that pf will correctly predict the nth symbol for all n

22、 m. That is, pf learns to predict e.Now we can construct an evader ef using the program that implements pf modified to complement the binary symbols it writes to its output tape. The proof that ef learns to evade all predictors in Pf is the same as the proof that pf that learns to predict all evader

23、s in Ef, with the obvious interchange of roles for predictors and evaders. This tells us that in the adversarial sequence prediction game, if either side has a sufficient advantage in computational resources to simulate all possible opponents then it can always win. So the game can be interpreted as

24、 a computational resources arms race.Note that a predictor or evader making truly random choices of its output symbols, with 0 and 1 equally likely, will win half the rounds no matter what its opponent does. But Proposition 1 tells us that an algorithm making pseudo-random choices will be defeated b

25、y an opponent with a sufficient advantage in computing resources.3. Software ExperimentsAdversarial sequence prediction is a computational resources arms race for algorithms using unrealistically large computational resources. Whether this is also true for algorithms using more modest computational

26、resources can best be determined by software experiments. I have done this for a couple algorithms that use lookup tables to learn their opponents behavior. The size of the lookup tables is the measure of computational resources. The predictor and evader start out with the same size lookup tables (a

27、 parameter can override this) but as they win or lose at each round the sizes of their lookup tables are increased or decreased. The software includes a parameter for growth of total computing resources, to simulate non-zero-sum games. Occasional random choices are inserted into the game, at a frequ

28、ency controlled by a parameter, to avoid repeating the same outcome in the experiments. The software for running these experiments is available online 8.Over a broad range of parameter values that define the specifics of these experiments, one opponent eventually gets and keeps all the computing res

29、ources. Thus these experiments provide evidence that adversarial sequence prediction is an unstable computational resources arms race for reasonable levels of computational resources.Interestingly, the game can be made stable, with neither opponent able to keep all the resources, by increasing the f

30、requency of random choices. It is natural and desirable that simple table-lookup algorithms should be unable to predict the behavior of the systems pseudo-random number algorithm. But more sophisticated algorithms could learn to predict pseudo-random sequences.The adversarial sequence prediction gam

31、e would make an interesting way to compare AGI implementations. Perhaps future AGI conferences could sponsor competitions between the AGI systems of different researchers.4. AI EthicsArtificial intelligence (AI) is often depicted in science fiction stories and movies as a threat to humans, and the i

32、ssue of AI ethics has emerged as a serious subject 9, 10, 11. Yudkowsky has proposed an effort to produce a design for AGI whose friendliness toward humans can be proved as it evolves indefinitely into the future 12. Leggs blog includes a debate with Yudkowsky over whether such a proof is possible 1

33、3. Legg produced a proof that it is not possible to prove what an AI will be able to achieve in the physical world, and Yudkowsky replied that he is not trying to prove what an AI can achieve in the physical world but merely trying to prove that the AI maintains friendly intentions as it evolves int

34、o the indefinite future. But intentions must be implemented in the physical world, so proving any constraint on intentions requires proving that the AI is able to achieve a constraint on the implementation of those intentions in the physical world. That is, if you cannot prove that the AI will be ab

35、le to achieve a constraint on the physical world then you cannot prove that it will maintain a constraint on its intentions.Adversarial sequence prediction highlights a different sort of issue for AI ethics. Rather than taking control from humans, AI threatens to give control to a small group of hum

36、ans. Financial markets, economic competition in general, warfare and politics include variants of the adversarial sequence prediction game. One reasonable explanation for the growing income inequality since the start of the information economy is the unstable computational resources arms race associ

37、ated with this game. Particularly given that in the real world algorithm quality is often an important computational resource. As the general intelligence of information systems increases, we should expect increasing instability in the various adversarial sequence prediction games in human society a

38、nd consequent increases in economic and political inequality. This will of course be a social problem, but will also provide an opportunity to generate serious public interest in the issues of AI ethics.References1J. Schmidhuber. The Speed Prior: A New Simplicity Measure Yielding Near-Optimal Comput

39、able Predictions. In J. Kivinen and R. H. Sloan, editors, Proceedings of the 15th Annual Conference on Computational Learning Theory (COLT 2002), Sydney, Australia, Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, pages 216-228. Springer, 2002. http:/www.idsia.ch/juergen/coltspeed/coltspeed.html2Hutter, M.

40、 Universal Artificial Intelligence: Sequential Decisions based on Algorithmic Probability. Springer, Berlin, 2004. 300 pages. http:/www.idsia.ch/marcus/ai/uaibook.htm3Hutter, M. and S. Legg. Proc. A Formal Measure of Machine Intelligence. 15th Annual Machine Learning Conference of Belgium and The Netherlands (Benelearn 2006), pages 73-80. http:/www.idsia.ch/idsiareport/IDSIA-10-06.pdf4Legg, S. Is there an Elegant Univers

展开阅读全文
相关资源
猜你喜欢
相关搜索

当前位置:首页 > 教育教学 > 成人教育


备案号:宁ICP备20000045号-2

经营许可证:宁B2-20210002

宁公网安备 64010402000987号